For those who have lived lives of bliss and were previously unaware of the argument, it goes like this:
cpdavey24’s formulation
cpdavey24’s
formulation in words (BS5)
Assertion:
it is possible
that
it is necessary that (there exists a being x) [where]
x is a Maximally Excellent being
Premise:
(IF) it is possible that it is
necessary that (there exists a being
x) [where] x is
a Maximally Excellent being
(THEN) it is necessary that (there exists a being x) [where]
x is a Maximally Excellent being
Conclusion:
Therefore it is necessary that (there
exists a being x) [where] x is a Maximally Excellent being
William
Lane Craig’s formulation
1. It
is possible that a maximally great being exists.
2. If
it is possible that a maximally great being exists, then a maximally great
being exists in some possible world.
3. If a
maximally great being exists in some possible world, then it exists in every
possible world.
4. If a
maximally great being exists in every possible world, then it exists in the
actual world.
5. If a
maximally great being exists in the actual world, then a maximally great being
exists.
6. Therefore,
a maximally great being exists.
(For
completeness, there is also the version presented in The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology (which ontologicalme@RF provided, along with
the correction at step 11):
I’ve
basically not bothered with this last “proof” for a couple of reasons, one
being that it’s rather inaccessible to the casual reader [and, to be honest, me], the other will be
touched on shortly.)
My
objection to the Ontological Argument in general, and Plantinga’s specifically,
is that the possibility of a thing, or even the possibility of the necessity of
thing, doesn’t by itself make that thing necessary.
It
should not be controversial that:
1. a thing may be either
possible (◊) or not possible (~◊) but not both, and
2. a thing may be either
necessary (□) or not necessary (~□) but not both.
Even
the fans of Plantinga’s BS5 seem to agree on these points.
Essentially,
the disagreement seems to centre on the meaning of “possible” and
“necessary”. If you look at the freely
available (and apparently well regarded) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (entry
on Modal Logic), you will find a discussion of necessity,
including the following:
The
system K is too weak to provide an adequate account of necessity. The
following axiom is not provable in K, but it is clearly desirable.
(M) □A->A
(M)
claims that whatever is necessary is the case.
A
little further on it continues with:
One
could engage in endless argument over the correctness or incorrectness of these
and other iteration principles for □ and ◊. The controversy can be partly
resolved by recognizing that the words ‘necessarily’ and ‘possibly’, have many
different uses. So the acceptability of axioms for modal logic depends on which
of these uses we have in mind.
In
other words, in K you can’t get from
a statement that a thing is necessary to a statement that that thing actually
is and the very validity of an axiom rests on what you mean by “necessity” and
“possibility” (via the meanings of “necessarily” and “possibly”).
Let’s
not focus too deeply, therefore, on what “necessity” and “possibility”
mean. What I’d like to do instead is
introduce the following “neopolitonian axioms” with the actual axiom designation
following in (round brackets) or
[square brackets]:
n1: If A is possible, then it is not possible that A is not possible … ◊A->~◊~◊A …
[double negation]
n2: If A is necessary, then it is not necessary that A is not necessary … □A->~□~□A … [double negation]
n3: If A is necessary, then A is
possible … □A->◊A … (D)
Because
I am a visual sort of person, I present n3 in a Venn Diagram:
In other words, the set of things that are necessary fit into the set of things that are possible.
If
we use Transposition we can reach:
n4: If A is not possible, then A
is not necessary … ~◊A->~□A
Here’s
a visual n4:
In
other words, if something is in the set of things that are not possible they
are necessarily not part of the set of things that are necessary (or ~◊A->~□□A and since □□A->□A therefore ~◊A->~□A).
Now
that I have an excuse to present such things visually, I want to illustrate
that in the real world there is an intersection of things that are not
necessary but are nevertheless possible (◊A ∩ ~□A).
It’s possible for me to be a dwarf, but it’s not necessary. It’s possible for my car to be green, but
it’s not necessary. Visually:
Now
if Craig (via Plantinga) is arguing that if a thing is possible then it must
therefore exist, then they surely have a problem. There is clearly a category of things which
are possible and not necessary and therefore Craig and Plantinga cannot reach
the conclusion that they are grasping at.
The
best they can do is argue all the way to “necessity” in K (which they might attempt by writing long extremely inaccessible "proofs" in arcane logic schemas which might easily mean absolutely nothing once you decode it and will be a complete waste of time for the poor bastard who attempts that decoding effort), at which point they are stuck because K is too weak to get you from necessity to existence (so that huge decoding effort was a waste of time even before that poor bastard started). If they want to, eager theists can use a stronger system of
logic which can get them from necessity to existence, but then they can’t reach
necessity from possibility. So, what
they do is use a weak form like K up until they
achieve necessity, then they swap taxi-cabs and
pretend that they have been using a stronger system of logic all the time.
---------------------------
The SEP
entry on modal logic actually addresses the confusion that
leads to BS5, so let’s have a quick look at that:
It is
interesting to note that S5 can be formulated equivalently by adding (B)
to S4. The axiom (B) raises an important point about the
interpretation of modal formulas. (B) says that if A is the case,
thenA is necessarily possible. One might argue that (B) should
always be adopted in any modal logic, for surely if A is the case, then
it is necessary that A is possible. However, there is a problem with
this claim that can be exposed by noting that ◊□A->A is provable
from (B). So ◊□A->A should be acceptable if (B) is.
However,◊□A->A says that if A is possibly necessary, then A
is the case, and this is far from obvious. Why does (B) seem obvious,
while one of the things it entails seems not obvious at all? The answer is that
there is a dangerous ambiguity in the English interpretation of A->□◊A.
We often use the expression ‘If A then necessarily B’ to express
that the conditional ‘if A then B’ is necessary. This
interpretation corresponds to □(A->B). On other occasions, we mean
that if A, then B is necessary: A->□B. In English, ‘necessarily’
is an adverb, and since adverbs are usually placed near verbs, we have no natural
way to indicate whether the modal operator applies to the whole conditional, or
to its consequent. For these reasons, there is a tendency to confuse (B):
A->□◊A with □(A->◊A). But □(A->◊A) is
not the same as (B), for □(A->◊A) is already a theorem of M,
and (B) is not. One must take special care that our positive reaction to
□(A->◊A) does not infect our evaluation of (B). One simple
way to protect ourselves is to formulate B in an equivalent way using
the axiom:◊□A->A, where these ambiguities of scope do not arise.
This
makes me wonder if this confusion is fundamentally an American English
issue. It’s been a constant irritation
to me that Americans insist on using poetic English literally:
All that glisters is not
gold – Merchant of Venice, Shakespeare
This
is poetic/archaic, it is not correct modern English. Think on it for a moment. Imagine that I suffer from dwarfism and I
have seven children, I could say when addressing a session of Little People
Anonymous:
·
“Hello, I am neopolitan, I am a dwarf; all of
my seven children are not dwarves” or
·
“Hello, I am neopolitan, I am a dwarf; not
all of my seven children are dwarves” or
·
“Hello, I am neopolitan, I am a dwarf; all of
my seven children are dwarves”
When
shown together like this, we can clearly see that I am making three different
hypothetical statements. I have seven
children with dwarfism, seven children without dwarfism or seven children, some
of whom have dwarfism (but am conveying something by highlighting those who
don’t have dwarfism, perhaps I am about to launch into a discussion of how I
adopted four of my children in order to have someone in the house who can reach
the top shelves and how silly I felt when I realised that I could have just
bought a stepladder).
Returning
to Shakespeare, some things that glister actually are gold, otherwise the
claim makes no sense … so if he was writing in proper English today, and wanted
to convey his message clearly rather than poetically, he would have written
“Not all that glisters is gold” or, alternatively, “Some things that glister
are not gold”. It does amuse me that I
can say “All Americans are not smart”, while pointing to some exception to the hypothetical
assertion “All Americans are smart” (for example Bush when talking to
non-Republicans and Clinton when talking to non-Democrats), and the vast
majority of Americans won’t be offended.
I do know that some Americans are frighteningly intelligent, it’s merely
the little grammatical anomaly that I find amusing and that amusement allows me
to overcome some of the frustration associated with American cultural
imperialism.
Anyhoo,
Americans (and increasingly the rest of the English-talkificating world) are thus
rendered incapable of placing adverbs correctly and so, as a consequence, when
someone says “it is necessary that, if A,
then it is possible that A” it should
come as no great surprise that there is confusion as to whether this means □(A->◊A) or A->□◊A.
An example
of an equivalent confusion is in cpdavey24’s attempt to prove the validity of
BS5, the “cpdavey24 proof” (note that he uses p rather than A, so I
must make the one additional assertion to bring his “proof” in line with the
notation at SEP, that p<-->A. I’ll provide
clarifications in
green and English language versions in gold):
1. ◊□A (Assumption
for Conditional Proof (CP)) – this is just the starting position
– it is possible
that A is necessary
2. ~□A (Assumption
for Reductio Ad Absurdum (RAA)) – indication of intent to prove A is
necessary by showing that the claim that A is not necessary is
absurd, given the assumption that A is possibly necessary
3. ~~◊~A
(2 E2) – grouping brackets have been omitted, should
read ~(~◊~A), uses the rule (E2) that if a thing is necessary, then it cannot
be impossible
– it is not impossible that A is not actual
– it is not impossible that A is not actual
4. ◊~A (3
Double Negation (DN)) – if it is not the case that it is not
possible that A is not actual, then it follows that …
– it is possible that A is not actual
– it is possible that A is not actual
5. □|
◊~A (4 S5-reit) – this appears to be a
reinterpretation of (5), the valid form of which states that ◊A®□◊A
– it is necessary that it is possible that A is not actual
– it is necessary that it is possible that A is not actual
6. □◊~A
(5 nec intro) – the introduction of
necessity, now states that it is necessary that it is possible that A is not
actual
– it is necessary that it is possible that A is not actual
– it is necessary that it is possible that A is not actual
7. □~□~~A
(6 E1) – grouping brackets have been omitted, should
read □(~□~(~A)), uses the rule (E1) that if a thing is possible, then it cannot
be necessarily non-actual
– it is necessary that it is unnecessary that A is not not actual
– it is necessary that it is unnecessary that A is not not actual
8. □~□A
(7 DN) – if it is necessary that it not be necessary
that A not be not actual then it follows that …
– it is necessary that it is unnecessary that A is actual
– it is necessary that it is unnecessary that A is actual
9. ~◊~~□A
(8 E2) – grouping brackets have been omitted, should
read ~◊~(~□A), uses E2 again
– it is impossible that it is not unnecessary that A is actual
– it is impossible that it is not unnecessary that A is actual
10. ~◊□A
(9 DN) – if it is not possible that it not be not
necessary that A is actual then it follows that …
– it is impossible that it is necessary that A is actual
– it is impossible that it is necessary that A is actual
11. ◊□A
& ~◊□A (1,10 Conjunction) – indicates
that from 2 we arrive at 10, which conflicts with the starting position, the
necessity of A cannot be both possible and impossible, so the claim is that the
absurd is achieved
12. ~~□A
(1-11 RAA) – the negation of 2, since the proof seems to
indicate that 2 cannot be true and only other option is not 2
– it is not unnecessary that A is actual
– it is not unnecessary that A is actual
13. □A (12 DN) – simple
double negation
– it is necessary that A is actual
– it is necessary that A is actual
14. ◊□A -> □A Q.E.D. (1-13 CP) – a “look at me” statement, claiming that it
has been proven that …
– if something is possibly necessary then it is necessary
– if something is possibly necessary then it is necessary
cpdavey24
did want me to make comment on this proof, so here here’s my comment in the
form of a question: cpdavey24, does it not feel strange that you are obliged to
use an RAA approach?
Let’s try
it without:
1. ◊□A (Initial
position)
2. A <--> ~B (Assumption for Logical Fiddle)
3. ◊□~B
(Substitution of 2 into 1)
4. ~~◊~~□~B (3 double DN)
5. ~□~□~B (4 E2)
6. ~□~□A (Substitution
of 2 into 5)
7. □A (6 n2)
8. ◊□A -> □A Q.E.D. (1-7)
This is a
superior proof since it doesn’t rely on the distracting RAA. But it’s still wrong. Note that the substitution steps (A <--> ~B) aren’t really necessary, they are just a
distraction.
1. ◊□A (Initial position)
2. ~~◊~~□A (1 double DN)
3. ~□~□A (2 E2)
4. □A (3 n2)
5. ◊□A -> □A Q.E.D. (1-4)
Where’s
the error?
Well, for
starters, I used n2 in reverse, which isn’t valid. However, I also think that there might be an
issue with using generating a “not” via a double negative in front of a □ symbol and then using it with
the preceding ◊ symbol.
However,
if I now try to use cpdavey24’s RAA approach:
1. ◊□A (Initial position)
2. ~□A (Assumption
for RAA)
3. ~~□~□A (2 n2)
– note that this is no longer in reverse, so it is now valid
4. ~~~◊~~□A (3 E2)
– note that I am now using E2 in the same
direction as cpdavey24 did
5. ~◊□A (4 DN)
– note that I am now using DN in the same direction as
cpdavey24 did
6. ◊□A & ~◊□A (1,5 Conjunction)
7. ~~□A (2-6 RAA)
8. □A (7 DN)
9. ◊□A -> □A Q.E.D. (1-8)
So what
we have is what appears to be a perfectly valid proof, despite the fact that I
just showed you there was an error in it.
All I’ve done is hidden it with a Reductio Ad Absurdum.
Suddenly,
it doesn’t seem as strange that cpdavey24 used the RAA approach.
I’ll
leave it to the reader (perhaps even cpdavey24) to discover whether the error
in the “cpdavey24 proof” can be found when it is run forward, rather than in
reverse. If you do find it, feel free to
post it in the comments section.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Feel free to comment, but play nicely!
Sadly, the unremitting attention of a spambot means you may have to verify your humanity.