it
is unreasonable to assess the morality of another person’s ethical structure
Yes,
I did write this and I stand by it. But
please note the context in which I wrote the words, namely:
It
seems that once the argument that ethical structures are inherently amoral has
been accepted, it is unreasonable to assess the morality of another person’s ethical
structure – which would be inherently amoral from their perspective.
Also
note that later in the same article, I wrote:
An
example might be useful here, since I appear to be straying very close to the
form of moral and cultural relativism that is better labelled as “moral
cowardice”.
This
was not the first time that I have addressed concerns with moral relativism,
having touched on it in The Problem with Sam. However, after listening to a little
discussion piece, “Moral Relativism”, I
realise that it’s an issue of such import that it warrants further attention.
When
discussing the problem with Sam, I wrote about how moral relativism is accused of
being equivalent to moral nihilism which,
at least in a pejorative sense, implies a belief that nothing is moral or
immoral. A stricter definition of moral
nihilism refers to the lack of intrinsic morality. This kinder perspective does not deny the
possibility of an emergent morality, within the context of a society, but does
deny the claim that morality is somehow inherent to the universe.
If
one listens to conservatives such as Roger Scrunton, one gets the impression
that those who subscribe to moral relativism have totally abandoned the idea of
morality, as if there are only two choices: moral absolutism or nothing. Apparently, the moral relativist makes a claim
along the lines of “No-one else may judge me.
Only I may judge me.”
At
the risk of appearing to agree with Scrunton, such a claim is patent nonsense –
but not even the most intellectually feeble-minded moral relativist makes this
claim. What Scrunton is alluding to is
some form of inwards-looking normative moral relativism,
but the standard phrasing and I dare say the standard understanding is outwards-looking. Moral relativism is not so much a question of
what other people may and may not do with respect to me, but more about what I
ought to do with respect to other people.
It’s an expression of a(n emergent) moral obligation to be tolerant,
not a moral injunction against judging others at all.
It
would appear that Scrunton argues against a somewhat extreme, self-obsessed and
rather conservative form of moral relativism – or at least moral relativism
viewed darkly through a conservative lens.
It should be no surprise that he takes a dim view of moral relativism,
since tolerance (2) is a liberal sort of concept. Scrunton
himself seems to prefer the term toleration. Unfortunately, these two terms have merged to
the extent Wikipedia’s entry on tolerance
provides in its definition a link to toleration, even though the two words have
quite distinct implications.
If
I am characterised by tolerance, I am free from bigotry – I don’t look down on
those who are different as being inferior or bad. If on the other hand, I am characterised by
toleration, I may be bigoted – I may see others as inferior or bad, but I put
up with them.
------------------------------------------
Let
us return to the ethical structure and the confusion about inviolability of the
structure. I do not wish to imply that you
cannot make a moral judgment regarding other people, nor that one should not
make such a moral judgment, even if they have a different ethical structure to
yours. All I am saying is that you
cannot justify making a moral judgment on an ethical structure, your
own or theirs.
In
my argument, the whole point of an ethical structure is to make moral judgments
on other people, and thereby assess whether they constitute a threat. As an individual, therefore, it is rational
to expect that you will be subject to the moral judgments of others. In fact, it is rational to welcome those
judgments.
If
someone were to tell me that they did not want me to make moral judgements on
them, my first inclination would be to ask myself why. How would someone benefit by me not making a
moral judgment on them? Perhaps by
evading my finely tuned threat detection mechanisms? Equally, if other people make no moral
judgments on me, how are they going to assess whether I am threat to them? If no moral judgments are made, how can I
signal to them that I am benign? I could
make my good intentions explicit by telling them that I am not a threat, but if
they don’t make any assessment as to whether I am telling the truth then my
declaration of good intent means nothing.
A
sort of moral relativism is that is entirely rational exists in tier six, the
lowest tier of the ethical structure that I recently discussed. This layer involves conformance with a largely
arbitrary set of societal standards and cultural mores, along with rules and
laws which are derived from the upper tiers.
Some of these rules exist simply to be obeyed. The more irrational such a rule is the better
it functions, since obedience to an irrational rule is a better indicator of an
inclination to conform than obedience to a rational rule. For a good exposition on this sort of
argument, I can heartily recommend Michael Shermer’s How We Believe.
An
example of an irrational rule that indicates our inclination to conform is the
wearing of a tie. Ties are uncomfortable
and, almost without exception, look rather stupid. They can be positively dangerous, especially
when using a shredder. The only valid
reason for wearing a tie is in order to send a signal that you conform (even if
you have a tie in your uniform, you are still indicating an inclination to
conform by wearing it – perhaps only to the extent that you are not expelled or
sacked). All societies and social groups
have a range of such rules applying to not only what we wear, or how we cut our
hair or colour our bodies, but also how we eat, what we eat, how we talk, how
we sit, stand and walk, what we do on certain days of the week, who we have sex
with and how, what animals we cultivate and which we have as pets and so on.
It
is entirely reasonable to take a relativist stance on these “conformance rules”
since they are arbitrary, even if they seem alien or odd to us. However, when it comes to the five main moral
injunctions, or tiers one to five, moral relativism is no longer a reasonable
stance to take.
If
it is ever unclear whether tolerance of an act is appropriate or not, I suggest
asking yourself the following two questions:
Is
any innocent party harmed by the act?
Is
the act fair?
If
an act is fair and no innocent party is harmed by an act, then I suggest that
tolerance is warranted. If an act is not
fair, or it leads to actual harm, then I suggest that tolerance is not
warranted.
------------------------------------------
By
an “innocent party” I mean someone not involved in the act, meaning that
consensual harm is excluded. Consensual
harm could be such things as involvement in a boxing match, being tattooed,
pierced or ritually scarred, or engaging in sexual activity that is believed by
some to condemn the participants to posthumous suffering or incorporates play
which may be literally harmful (so long as such activity is consensual).
I
don’t consider “being offended” as universally equivalent to “being
harmed”. In some instances offence may
cross a line and thus constitute harm – an example being racial vilification.
In
other instances, however, taking offence can be inappropriate – for example the
offence one might feel when witness to the paucity of a builder’s vocabulary,
especially in regard to adjectives but also adverbs, verbs, nouns and
expletives. (“#@&*! The #@&*ing
little #@&*ers totally #@&*ing #@&*ed! We’re #@&*ed!”).
You
might be justified in feeling offended if the school principal spoke like that,
unless he came from Australia (and more specifically Queensland), but that sort
of language is usually expected from a tradesman. You might even be somewhat disconcerted to
hear one say “Oh my! This irritating
thing (the name for which I am temporarily unable to recall due to a sudden
onset of incoherent rage) appears to be irrevocably impaired! This is likely to have an adverse and maybe
even devastating effect on our rather tight schedule and consequently on my
finances as well as the economic viability of my company as a whole. My distress at this situation is of such
import that I am sorely tempted to abandon my endeavours and decamp forthwith, in
my tastefully appointed and decal-adorned utility vehicle, with the intent of relocating
with immediate effect to the nearest establishment providing alcoholic
refreshment at a reasonable price.” (For
the Queenslanders among us, that last sentence can be roughly translated as “#@&*
it, ’m’gar’n’th’pub.”)
No comments:
Post a Comment
Feel free to comment, but play nicely!
Sadly, the unremitting attention of a spambot means you may have to verify your humanity.