John Hawthorne recently gave a presentation
on fine-tuning from Bayesian perspective to the Royal Institute of Philosophy’s
Religious Epistemology Conference. It’s
basically the same presentation as given a couple of years ago, but with a different conclusion.
During both versions of the presentation he provides an analogy which he
attributes to Jonathan Weisberg, although he has modified it somewhat – the
original argument by Weisberg is available here. (I will discuss that argument in another article, and
link to Weisberg's argument again, so there’s no need to rush off to read it just yet!)
Hawthorne’s (2013) version goes a
little like this:
There are two cell blocks in a prison from which a prisoner is
about to be released. In one block, A,
there are 99 innocent prisoners and one guilty one. In the other block, B, there are 99 guilty
prisoners and one innocent one.
(For the purposes of the exercise we can imagine that the prison
is located in a country (or county) which is devoted to locking up a large proportion of
their populace – say a smidgen under 1,000 in every 100,000 – in order to keep
their previously thriving law and order, justice and incarceration industries
afloat. Sadly, in order to keep up the
supply to prisons, those at the front end have now resorted to processing
people for such crimes as “walking on the cracks in the pavement”, “possession
of an offensive wife”, “smelling of foreign food” and “looking at me in a funny
way” (thanks largely to this hypothetical country’s version of Constable Savage). Fortunately, there still sufficient disparity
in wealth to drive the level of crime needed to ensure that about 50% of those
in prison are bona fide criminals.)
The decision as to which prisoner is to be released is to be made
by one of two officials, Mr Random, who will just pick a prisoner at random
(irrespective of whether he or she is guilty or not), and Miss Justice, who
will only release a prisoner if that prisoner is innocent.
What we don’t know is who makes the decision to release the
prisoner, and we don’t know any details regarding how they make their
decisions, beyond what has already been revealed.
Say that the prisoner who is released was one of those put away
for “wearing a loud shirt in a built-up area in the early hours of the morning”
(in other words he is guilty of no more than fashion crime). What can we say about the likelihood that Mr
Random or Miss Justice released the prisoner?
If we know nothing other than that the
prisoner is (relatively) innocent, we could assume that it’s 66% likely that Miss
Justice was in charge of the release, because she doesn’t release the guilty,
so innocents will be released by her 100% of the time and only 50% of the time
by Mr Random.
But what if we also know what cell
block the prisoner came from? Say that
the prisoner came from cell block B, in which there was only one innocent
prisoner? This fact, according to
Hawthorne, makes it even more likely that the person in charge of the release
was Miss Justice, because there is a 1% chance of Mr Random selecting the
innocent from that cell block, if he were in charge, but a 100% chance if Miss
Justice was responsible.
While Hawthorne’s conclusion does
seem eminently reasonable when he’s presenting the argument, there are at least
two hidden assumptions. Hawthorne
doesn’t hide one of the assumptions in question, explaining it some depth. Before I get onto that, however, I want to
ram home Hawthorne’s variant of the analogy a little.
Innocence is analogous to life (or
perhaps “life-permittingness”) and Miss Justice is analogous to a designer with
a preference (in this case, a preference for innocence) who is standing in for a
god with a life fixation while Mr Random is a reification of blind luck or
chance.
The argument then goes that if
“life-permittingness” is highly unlikely in the universe (à la the fine-tuning
argument), then the likelihood of a designer of the universe who prefers
universes with life (perhaps because life is necessary for something the
designer is really aiming for, almost invariably presumed to be intelligence)
becomes correspondingly high. Therefore
god.
However, as suggested, there are at
least two hidden assumptions.
We don’t know how the prisoner was
selected and in order to get the figures that Hawthorne reaches, we have to assume
that:
a.
it is equally likely, for any given release, that Miss Justice or
Mr Random should be in charge, and
b.
when Miss Justice is in charge, she first selects the cell block
at random, and then somehow selects an innocent prisoner.
Hawthorne spends quite some time to
try to convince us that the second assumption is reasonable. (He just breezes over the first assumption
which is okay, I suppose, since he did warn us that the presentation would be
breezy.) But are either of these
assumptions reasonable in terms of the analogy?
I’d say that neither of them is
reasonable at all. I am tempted to let
the first assumption slide for the same reason that I am often willing to
concede (for the sake of the argument with a theist) a deist god – one which
lights the metaphorical fuze for the Big Bang and then is never seen or heard from
again. A universe created by such a god
that subsequently resulted in us would be indistinguishable from a universe
which, by mere happenstance, resulted in us.
But it’s worth noting that by virtue of the underlying assumption, the
hypothesis of intelligent design is given an initial boost to a likelihood of 50%.
The second assumption, however,
needs some attention. Hawthorne
criticises Weisberg for suggesting that there is “no reason” to believe that
Miss Justice would not use the selection method assumed in his (Hawthorne’s)
version of the analogy. Weisberg writes:
“We have no reason to think the judge cares where the pardoned prisoner is
housed, but as it happens there are (99) innocent prisoners in cell block A,
and only 1 in cell block B.” Note that
Weisberg used a figure of 9 innocents in cell block A, but I am going to stick
with Hawthornesque figures. Hawthorne
suggests that even if we are only 5% certain that Miss Justice will use that assumed
method, then we will have a significant certainty that she selected the
prisoner to be released – if the prisoner was both innocent and from cell block
B.
There are two issues. The first is that the figures are possibly
not as impressive as they are made out to be and the second is that there are
reasons why Miss Justice would not use the assumed method (and I believe that
this fact is inherent in Weisberg’s argument, but it has been overlooked by
Hawthorne).
First the figures. On the basis that an innocent is released,
given some apparently trivial assumptions, we can reach a conclusion that it is
66.7% likely that Miss Justice was in charge of the decision:
Pr(J|I) = ( Pr(J&A&I) + Pr(J&B&I) )
/ ( Pr(J&A&I) + Pr(J&B&I) + Pr(R&A&I) +
Pr(R&B&I) )
= (100/400 + 100/400) / (100/400 +
100/400 + 99/400 + 1/400)
= 200/300
= 66.7%
If we know that the prisoner is
from cell block B, as well as being innocent, we use a different equation:
Pr(J|B&I) = ( Pr(J&B&I) )
/ ( Pr(J&B&I) + Pr(R&B&I) )
= (100/400)
/ (100/400 + 1/400)
= 100/101
= 99.01%
This looks good, but it is
contingent on a base likelihood (prior) of 50% for Miss Justice being in charge
(as well as the assumption of a 50-50 toss on which cell block to select a
prisoner from). Let’s assume instead
that it is somewhat less likely that she is in charge*:
Pr(J|I) = ( Pr(J&A&I) + Pr(J&B&I) )
/ ( Pr(J&A&I) + Pr(J&B&I) + Pr(R&A&I) +
Pr(R&B&I) )
= (100/20000 + 100/20000) / (100/20000 + 100/20000 + 9801/20000 + 99/20000)
= 200/10100
= 1.98%
Pr(J|B&I) = ( Pr(J&B&I) )
/ ( Pr(J&B&I) + Pr(R&B&I) )
=
(100/2000) / (100/2000 + 9/2000)
= 100/109
= 50.25%
This result could easily impress Plantinga, who
thinks that “about half” suffices as proof for his god, but it’s merely a
coincidence. If we make the base
likelihood of Miss Justice being in charge 1/1000, while holding everything
else constant, then the Pr(J|B&I) figure falls away to less than 10%. Make it 1 in a million and we get one
hundredth of one per cent.
This might, perhaps, seem
unreasonable on my part – but one of the arguments that Hawthorne is likely to
mount in his defence is that there is “no reason” to assume that the base
likelihood of Miss Justice being in charge (or god being the intelligent
designer) is as low as, or lower, than 1/100.
But Hawthorne himself suggests that we shouldn’t use “no reason”
arguments. (If he has other arguments,
I’ll leave it to him to present them.)
From my perspective it seems like
Hawthorne is trying to bump the likelihood of god as designer to levels that
are statistically significant, by means of assuming a pre-existing likelihood
that is already reasonably high. It
occurs to me that this is a form of fine-tuning of its own, may be
meta-fine-tuning – given that the supporting analysis favouring the idea that
the fine-tuning argument might be significant must be fine-tuned within a
narrowish band.
Now that we have touched again on
the issue of “no reason”, let’s move towards a consideration as to whether
there truly is no reason to believe that Miss Justice might choose a particular
method of selecting prisoners for release.
Hawthorne does concede that it is possible that Miss Justice might use a
different approach than selecting a cell block at random and then using some criteria
to select a prisoner for release from that cell block. He suggests considering a 50-50 chance that
she selects a prisoner at random from the population of 100 innocent prisoners.
Let’s do that:
Using the same processes as above,
we arrive at a Pr(J|I) of 66.7% again, but a Pr(J|B&I) of 98.08%, which
isn’t a huge drop below 99%. But the
consequences of a lower base likelihood of Miss Justice being in charge are interesting:
Now Pr(J|B&I), the figure we
are truly interested in, has dropped to 34.00%.
If we make the likelihood of Miss Justice being in charge 1/1000, we get
a Pr(J|B&I) of less than 5%.
Hawthorne, however, suggested that
we might only be 5% confident that his preferred method was being used, so:
Pr(J|I) does not shift from 66.7%,
but Pr(J|B&I) has dropped a little.
When we look at a less likely Miss Justice, this effect is amplified:
I would argue that we should not be
even 5% confident that Miss Justice would use the method that Hawthorne prefers. And I believe that this argument carries
across into the scenario that this analogy is being applied to.
Consider what Miss Justice
represents. She is order being compared against
random chaos. She doesn’t just select a
prisoner for release at random, she has rules that she follows, she’s rational,
she thinks, she’s intelligent. However,
what Hawthorne is trying to have us believe is that she will also be
inconsistent, she will only be semi-rational.
Not only will she allow herself to be chosen at random (despite the fact
that her colleague is known to release guilty prisoners, else the whole
scenario falls apart), but she will also allow a random element to enter her
considerations. This is not an analogy
for intelligent design, this is at best an analogy for semi-intelligent,
or capricious design – by an agent that is not fully in control.
We need to look more closely at the
possible methods that Miss Justice might use to make a choice. She might:
select an innocent prisoner at random (Ran)
select the most innocent prisoner (MIn)
select the most recently arrived innocent prisoner (MRe)
select the innocent prisoner who has served the longest (Lon)
select an innocent prisoner based on some other relevant factor
(like ill health, age or frailty) (ReF)
select an innocent prisoner based on an irrelevant factor (like
attractiveness, race or wealth) (IrF)
randomly select a cell block
then Ran
then MIn
then MRe
then Lon
then IrF
then ReF
select the cell block with most innocents
then Ran
then MIn
then MRe
then Lon
then IrF
then ReF
select the cell block with fewest innocents
then Ran
then MIn
then MRe
then Lon
then IrF
then ReF
select the cell block based on some other relevant factor (say
worst living conditions)
then Ran
then MIn
then MRe
then Lon
then IrF
then ReF
select the cell block based on some irrelevant factor (say the
results of the latest football game)
then Ran
then MIn
then MRe
then Lon
then IrF
then ReF
randomly select a grouping based on some criterion other than cell
block (perhaps by race, or gender, or hair colour, or height)
then Ran
then MIn
then MRe
then Lon
then IrF
then ReF
select a grouping with most innocents
… and so on
I have no intention of crunching
the numbers associated with all these options.
What I can say instead is that it begins to look unlikely that we can
justifiably claim that it’s 50-50 as to whether Miss Justice uses the selection
method preferred by Hawthorne. We can’t
really get a quantitative grip on the likelihoods though because we don’t know
how many other relevant and irrelevant factors might exist and how likely they
are to sway Miss Justice. (An argument that could be mounted here is that other
than innocent-guilt and cell block, the prisoners should be considered as
homogenous but I suspect that this will negatively affect the utility of the
analogy for design theorists.)
What we can do instead is get a qualitative
grip, based on what Miss Justice is supposed to be representing. She’s all about justice and rules –
specifically not about random chance – and if so, it is reasonable to assume
that she will reject any methodology that incorporates random chance or
irrelevant factors. Within the scenario
Miss Justice is not responsible for the distribution of prisoners and therefore
that distribution can be considered to be random – since she has no control
over which of the innocent prisoners is in cell block B. So, any consideration which does not take
into account the entire population of innocent prisoners will incorporate
random chance, and will be rejected as a feature within a selection method. (In terms of the analogy, this is equivalent
to suggesting that the intelligent designer does not play dice, that the notion
of omniscience is not abandoned – because if a being is omniscient, it follows
that the results of its actions cannot be random.)
This leaves us with Miss Justice
using a method that ensures that she selects an innocent prisoner based on some
relevant criterion. We
don’t know what that criterion is, but we don’t need to, since no matter what
she uses, the likelihood that, given the opportunity, she will pick a prisoner
from cell block B remains the same – assuming only that prisoners are
distributed randomly (at the hands of some other prison official). So, we can now crunch some numbers again:
If anyone wants to play with the
spreadsheet that generated these tables, it is available here. Because formatting can get messy when
fractions are used, I’ve used percentages in this version. I’ve also introduced colours to make things a
little easier – the cells with a yellow background are the only ones that you
can modify, but you can look at the equations in the other cells if you want to
check my work. (You can even fiddle with
the proportions of guilty and innocent prisoners, and put in figures that match
Weisberg’s, if that tickles your fancy.)
What the analysis tells us is that,
unless you make an unreasonable assumption about Miss Justice, the fact that it
is unlikely that an innocent prisoner should have been released from cell block
B does not provide us with any additional confidence that Miss Justice was
involved in the decision making process.
Similarly, the notion that the
universe appears to be fine-tuned for life does not provide any additional support
for the argument that there is an intelligent designer with a preference for
life. Any arguments from fine-tuning for
(intelligent) life are no better than an argument from the existence of
(intelligent) life. And all of us, at
least those of us who are sufficiently intelligent, have always been aware of
the existence of (intelligent) life.
---
I’d be overjoyed if I were able to
say that this result is precisely the result that Jonathan Weisman arrives at
in the referenced article. Sadly however,
his argument is somewhat different, the analogy is used differently and he eventually
argues that the situation is actually worse for the design
theorist that I have indicated so far.
The silver lining is that I am
pretty sure that Weisberg’s argument cleaves rather close to the one I want to
make about the different options for making life that a god might have. I’ll get to that in the continuation (in Weisberg's Prisoners).
(Weisberg does reach the same, or a
similar, conclusion but does so merely in passing without addressing any
potential criticism of the sort levelled by Hawthorne and, in doing so, he
calls on “divine indifference” which incorporates an element of random chance.)
---
* Please note that in his 2013 presentation, Hawthorne said that a likelihood of god at 1/100 is “pretty high”, so I don’t feel that am being unreasonable when I look at a base likelihood of 1/100 with respect to Miss Justice being in charge.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Feel free to comment, but play nicely!
Sadly, the unremitting attention of a spambot means you may have to verify your humanity.