It
has come to my attention that there are parallels between my thinking with
regard to ethical structures and
some of the thinking of Hobbes and Machiavelli.
I’d like to take this opportunity to point out the specific parallels
where I see them.
-------------------------------
Hobbes was
a tutor to the prince who later became Charles II of England, during the time
of the English Civil War (1642-1651).
These hostilities had a great impression on Hobbes who came to think
that, for a state and the subjects of that state, nothing was remotely as bad
as civil war. Specifically, he saw that
any excesses of a sovereign were the price that should be reasonably paid for
the protection provided by that sovereign.
Where
Hobbes begins to approach my theory is when he explains the nature of the
relationship between the subjects of a state and the sovereign, which he
described in terms of a social contract.
What is important to note here is that social contract is neither real
nor explicit, but rather it is a notional agreement between each individual and
the state.
Without
this social contract, Hobbes argued, the life of man would be “solitary, poor,
nasty, brutish, and short”.
Similarly,
without the morality that derives from our communal ethical structures (or
rather, perhaps, the common aspects of individually held ethical structures),
our lives would likely be solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short. I have postulated that individually held
ethical structures also have, as their lowest tier, social conventions – the
meat and potatoes of a notional social contract, not so much with a sovereign
but with society in general.
So,
in effect, there are similarities between the social contract implied by the
concept of an ethical structure as I developed and the social contract
discussed by Hobbes, and they have the same objective – survival.
If
there are other parallels, I’d be interested to discuss them, but until then,
no other similarity between my ponderings about ethical structures and
Hobbesian social contract theory should be assumed.
-------------------------------
With
regard to Machiavelli, I
must hasten to point out that he was not an ethicist per se and many observers (or at least those who take him
literally) characterise Machiavelli’s argument that the end justifies the means
as immoral, if not evil. That said, Machiavelli
did write about morality in relation to seizing and maintaining power in The Prince.
I
acknowledge two aspects of similarity between Machiavelli’s thinking and my own
(although, as with Hobbes, I’d be interested in discussing other perceived
parallels – but please don’t assume that my thinking parallels Machiavelli in
all areas).
Machiavelli
noted that while a prince is praised for keeping his word, he is also praised
for seeming
to keep his word and it is this seeming that is key (Ch. 18). Appearing to be moral (conformant) is
certainly key in my arguments regarding ethical structures. For the purposes of promoting your survival
it is essential that you are seen to be moral with regard to your
peers and superiors and somewhat less important that you are moral. If you are scrupulously honest, but appear to
be a lying, conniving cheat, you fail to benefit from your honesty. You would actually be at a disadvantage with
respect to a lying, conniving cheat who works hard at appearing to be
scrupulously honest, and you would benefit neither the veneer of honesty nor
the fruits that derive from being a lying, conniving cheat. Note the inclusion of the words “works hard” –
it often requires more of an effort to appear to be scrupulously honest when
one is a lying, conniving cheat than it is to be honest. Therefore, for the lazier among us, it is
rather more convenient to be truly honest, rather than just pretend.
However,
there are situations in which honesty is not the best policy. For example, there are times when the risks
associated with obeying the injunction against killing others are greater than
the risks associated with being identified as a killer. When morality no longer features strongly in the
optimal course of action, Machiavelli’s advice to the Prince becomes salient:
(The
Prince) should appear to be compassionate, faithful to his word, guileless, and
devout. And indeed he should be so. But his disposition should be such that, if
he needs to be the opposite, he knows how.
Machiavelli
describes this skill – knowing when to be uncompassionate, faithless, guileful
and profane – as a “virtue”. This should
however be taken in context.
Machiavelli
was a hardened realist rather than an idealist, and in the pages of The Prince,
he was providing (possibly ironic or satirical)
advice for successfully taking and maintaining power. He had recently witnessed the rise and fall
of the House of Borgia and
at the time of writing The Prince, the Medici family had recently returned to power in Florence. One of first acts by the Medici on retaking
power had been to arrest, torture and banish Machiavelli – notionally for
“conspiracy”, but possibly as payback for his involvement in expelling the
Medici in 1494, his earlier successes with his citizen-militia and his efforts
to defend the city-state republic of Florence against the return of Medici in
1512.
So,
The Prince was written in exile during a period of considerable political
instability. One could argue that Machiavelli’s
situation was analogous to that of Hobbes’, although whether he experienced what
could be considered a state of civil war is a matter of interpretation but the
Borgia had tried, quite brutally, to unify what is now central Italy. Such an argument finds support in the fact
that Machiavelli appeals to the Medici, who had tortured and banished him, to
unify central Italy.
If,
like Hobbes, Machiavelli had come to the conclusion that stability was
paramount, then it should be no surprise that there should be some parallels
between their thinking. The difference
lies in the perspective. Hobbes was
saying that, for the subject of a nation, subordination to the sovereign
(despite the behaviour of the sovereign) is the path to security. Machiavelli was saying that the security of
the sovereign (or Prince) relies on the sovereign acting in whatever manner
necessary to remain in power. In this
sense, knowing when to act immorally would indeed constitute a “virtue”.
Subordination
to a weak sovereign offers a subject little protection, so one can see that
Hobbes might well have argued that immoral behaviour that is necessary to
maintain the security of the sovereign would be entirely justifiable (although
he may have stopped short of labelling sovereign-maintaining immorality as
virtuous).
Similarly,
in respect to ethical structures, I have argued that the survival benefit
provided by acting morally is potentially negated if – when being moral is no
longer the strategy that will promote your survival – you are unable to “be the
opposite”.
Note,
however, that this sanctioning of immorality is caveated – both on the part of
the sovereign (or Prince) and the individual.
Immoral behaviour for the sake of immoral behaviour is not justified and
can be deleterious to security. Excesses
can lead to the removal of a sovereign - even Machiavelli, who rated fear more
highly than love as a motivator for the subjects of a Prince, warned against
letting fear become hatred. Untimely
immorality on the part of an individual can lead to punishment, withdrawal of
privileges, exclusion or even death (see The Bible for
an extensive list of infractions occasioning capital punishment).
-------------------------------
I’d like to stress
that although there may be some similarities between what Hobbes and Machiavelli
had to say and my musings on ethical structures, this should not be taken as
meaning that I subscribe unreservedly to either the Hobbesian or Machiavellian
schools of thought and that neither of them were (at least not directly nor
intentionally) sources from which my thinking was derived.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Feel free to comment, but play nicely!
Sadly, the unremitting attention of a spambot means you may have to verify your humanity.