“(T)here’s no reason to
think that God and evil are logically incompatible. There’s no explicit contradiction between them. But if the atheist means there’s some implicit contradiction between God and
evil, then he must be assuming some hidden premises which bring out this
implicit contradiction. But the problem
is that no philosopher has even been able to identify such premises. Therefore, the logical problem of evil fails
to the prove any inconsistency between God and evil.”
If
you read his article, you see that he goes on in the next paragraph to claim
that “it is widely agreed among contemporary philosophers that the logical
problem of evil has been dissolved. The
co-existence of God and evil is logically possible.” This is a bold claim, with no indication of
support given. I suspect that it’s
similar to the method of his madness, in that Craig is counting Christian
theologians as philosophers, then claiming that among that subset of
“philosophers”, there is wide agreement.
If so, then this is a deceptive claim.
We’ll just have to take a look to see whether the claim is defensible.
First
though, let’s look at the Problem of Evil itself. Variations of this argument existed well
before stories of Jesus of Nazareth arrived on the scene. It can be argued, and is in fact argued by
Craig himself, that the Book of Job is all about the Problem of Evil. The Problem of Evil was also mulled over by
the ancient Mesopotamians.
But
what is it?
Well,
in its most simple form, the problem revolves around the question of the nature
of God (that is specifically the Judeo-Christian god) and the existence of
evil. If God is omnipotent, omniscient
and omnibenevolent, then evil should not exist.
We’ll
work through these in reverse order.
Stephen Law
argues that there is no real reason to assume that any god, if it exists, is
going to be omnibenevolent. The
existence of natural evil, such as the starving of animals in droughts, can in
fact be better explained by an evil god who wants there to be suffering. If God is omnibenevolent, then His acts (and
His omissions) will always be good.
Therefore, logically, if there is evil in the universe, then it is not
due to any intentional act of commission or omission on the part of God.
One
might want to argue that perhaps, despite his best intentions, God is not
cognizant of natural evil. However, if
He is omniscient then there is literally nothing that God does not know.
Alternatively,
one might wish to argue that natural evil is a necessary consequence of some
higher plan that God has in place. In
other words, God could not achieve His objectives without the widespread
suffering that we observe on our planet.
However, this is a limitation on God’s power, in which case he is not
omnipotent.
No
matter how much you twist and turn, God must be impotent or ignorant or He has
knowingly chosen to create the universe to be the way it is, despite being able
to create it differently.
The
“great defence” that Craig refers to is Plantinga’s Free Will Defence which is a
variation on the defence raised by Irenaeus (130-202 C.E.) Note that Irenaean Theodicy was an early
Christian attempt to address the Problem of Evil, which was a problem for
the church, rather than for atheists.
The
argument runs a little like this: God has created the best of all possible worlds
which includes some evil but the great gifts (to humans) of Free Will and
salvation via the sacrifice of God’s Son/Self.
However,
this argument itself places limits on God, implying that He’s boxed into the
current arrangement by the consideration of ratios between evil and Free Will.
Remember
that God isn’t just tremendously powerful, he’s considered to be
omnipotent. Additionally, he isn’t just
working with the universe that pre-existed, he made it from scratch. The assertion that God could not make a
better universe in which evil and suffering were non-existent represents a
failure of imagination on the part of some theists.
1. It is possible that a
maximally great being exists.
2. If it is possible that a
maximally great being exists, then a maximally great being exists in some
possible world.
3. If a maximally great
being exists in some possible world, then it exists in every possible world.
4. If a maximally great
being exists in every possible world, then it exists in the actual world.
5. If a maximally great
being exists in the actual world, then a maximally great being exists.
6. Therefore, a maximally
great being exists.
There
are problems with this argument, as I’ve explained elsewhere,
and also with Craig’s defence of it (because he conflates Plantinga’s
ontological argument with that of Anselm).
However, note carefully that Plantinga uses “maximally great”, rather
than “infinitely great” or “omnipotent”.
This
is little more than a sleight of hand, we all know what he means by the term
“maximally great”. He doesn’t mean that,
say, Marilyn Vos Savant is in the running for being “maximally great”, or any
human being, no matter how strong, smart, artistic, generous, politically
correct etc etc etc. He specifically
means a god-like being, or even more specifically, God. By avoiding the term god-like, Plantinga
gives himself a little void of plausible deniability which he can use to
wriggle about in.
However,
despite the brilliance of Plantinga’s gymnastics, it is not difficult to us
puny humans to come up with a conception of the universe in which evil is not
necessary. The very fact that we can come
up with this idea, and the fact that this better universe does not exist, is
sufficient evidence, in and of itself, that an
omnipotent, omniscient, omnibenevolent god does not exist.
Now,
as soon as you suggest a sub-maximally great god (anything that is
less than infinitely great in all categories), you run into troubles because Plantinga’s ontological argument shows that it, unlike the proposed maximally great
being, doesn’t have to exist:
It is possible that a
sub-maximally great being exists.
If it is possible that a
sub-maximally great being exists, then (by virtue of being sub-maximally great)
the sub-maximally great being doesn’t have to exist in every possible world.
If a sub-maximally great
being doesn’t have to exist in every possible world, then it doesn’t have to
exist in the actual world.
If a sub-maximally great
being doesn’t have to exist in the actual world, then a sub-maximally great
being doesn’t have to exist.
Therefore, a sub-maximally
great being doesn’t have to exist.
In
conclusion then, there really aren’t any premises hidden by atheists in this
matter. The fundamental premise involved
is Christian, namely that God is perfect – perfectly powerful, perfectly
knowing and perfectly good.
If
Christians have given up that premise, they should do a better job of letting
the rest of us know.
--------------------------------------------
So,
is Craig’s claim that “it is widely agreed among contemporary philosophers that
the logical problem of evil has been dissolved” a valid claim?
Well,
no. The claim appears to be based on the
idea that Plantinga has resolved the issue once and for all. This might be agreed among certain
theologians and apologists, but not among philosophers.
As
the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
concludes:
There may be ways for
Plantinga to resolve the difficulties sketched above, so that
the Free Will Defense can be shown to be compatible with theistic doctrines
about heaven and divine freedom. As it stands, however, some important
challenges to the Free Will Defense remain unanswered. It is also important to
note that, simply because Plantinga’s particular use of free will in fashioning
a response to the problem of evil runs into certain difficulties, that does not
mean that other theistic uses of free will in distinct kinds of defenses or
theodicies would face the same difficulties.
Or,
at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
The problem, then, is that
Plantinga not only started out by focusing on very abstract versions of the
argument from evil, but also maintained this focus throughout. The explanation
of this may lie in the fact that Plantinga seems to have believed that if it
can be shown that the existence of God is neither incompatible with, nor
rendered improbable by, either (1) the mere existence of evil, or (2) the
existence of a specified amount of evil, then no philosophical problem remains.
People may find, of course, that they are still troubled by the existence of
specific evils, but this, Plantinga seems to (..) believe, is a religious
problem, and what is called for, he suggests, is not philosophical argument,
but “pastoral care”.
Plantinga's view here,
however, is very implausible. For not only can the argument from evil be
formulated in terms of specific evils, but that is the natural way to do so,
given that it is only certain types of evils that are generally viewed as
raising a serious problem with respect to the rationality of belief in God. To
concentrate exclusively on abstract versions of the argument from evil is
therefore to ignore the most plausible and challenging versions of the
argument.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Feel free to comment, but play nicely!
Sadly, the unremitting attention of a spambot means you may have to verify your humanity.