First get a test subject, give her a sledgehammer and put a
blindfold on her. Then take some eggs
and place them in a circle, at about sledgehammer distance from your test
subject.
Spin the test subject around a bit and then tell her to
swing down the sledgehammer onto the ground in front of her. Take the sledgehammer from her, lead her carefully away
from the test area, making sure she doesn't trip over any of the eggs. Then
you can remove the blindfold and give her a cup of tea and a biscuit.
---
Now you ask her to explain her position regarding whether or not
she hit an egg with the sledgehammer.
If I were the test subject, the first thing I'd do is check
my clothes to see if I had any egg fragments on me. Let's say there isn't, or at least she can't
see any egg product on her.
Does she know that she hit an egg? Note that she doesn't have any evidence that she
did.
Does she know that she didn't hit an egg? Note that the
absence of evidence is not evidence of absence. She could have missed it, or hit it in such a
way as to not get spattered. She doesn't have definitive evidence that she missed but she might think that she knows that she didn't
hit an egg. This would make her gnostic
with respect to egg-missing. She might, however, given the impossibility of evidence, remain
agnostic on this issue.
Note here that there are three possible epistemic
positions she could adopt:
She could claim to know that she
hit an egg
She could claim to know that she
missed all the eggs
She could state that she doesn't
know whether she hit or missed
You could also ask her what she believes with respect to
hitting or missing eggs and she could arrive at three similar doxic
positions:
She could believe that she hit an
egg
She could believe that she missed
all the eggs
She could state that she doesn't
believe anything with respect to whether she hit or missed
---
I'm tempted to replace epistemic with gnoseic,
as distinct from gnostic, but it's not a term that has taken off
and there's no firm definition of the word from which I have taken it
(gnoseology). Basically I want to distinguish
between that which is known (or thought to be known) and that which is believed
(including that which is known to be believed and not thought to be known). There are two Greek roots that could be used
for "regarding beliefs": doxa (common belief, opinion
or acceptance) and pistis (confidence, faith or trust). There are problems with both.
Doxology means "a liturgical formula of praise to God"
rather than being related to belief and pistiology means "the branch of
theology which treats of the place and authority of faith" or
"doctrine concerned with faith" while pisteology means "the
science of faith"(!) and both of these latter terms are far too close to
epistemology to avoid confusion, and replacing epistemology with gnoseology has its own problems. Just
work with me here and accept that by epistemic I mean "about
knowledge" and by doxic I mean "about belief (as distinct from faith)".
---
So, there are a limited number of workable combinations:
Believing (hit) and claiming to
know
Believing (hit) and accepting a
lack of knowledge
Not believing either and
accepting a lack of knowledge
Believing (miss) and accepting a
lack of knowledge
Believing (miss) and claiming to
know
It seems unreasonable to
claim to know that one hit an egg or missed all of them while also claiming to
believe the opposite. This sort of claim
works only as hyperbole, an expression of surprise or shock (as in "I know
I just won the lottery, but I have to keep pinching myself. I still don't believe it!") If you don't believe, you can't know - even
if you use Plantinga's modified epistemology you are still talking about
warranted true belief instead of the gold standard, justified
true belief.
Similarly, it seems unreasonable
to believe something and claim to know the opposite. You might express such a contradiction as some
sort of patriotic or loyal hyperbole - "I believe Moldovia is the best
country in the world, although I know it isn't really" or "I believe
my baby is the most beautiful ever, although I do know he looks like a miniature,
bald version of the later era Elvis", but in reality you believe that
Moldovia is, at best, only the second or third most liveable nation in the
world and that your child is has been beaten mercilessly with the ugly stick.
Let's put this in a table to
make it clear what I mean:
Know
Hit
|
Not
Know
|
Know
Miss
|
|
Believe
Hit
|
YES
|
YES
|
NO
|
Not
Believe
|
NO
|
YES
|
NO
|
Believe
Miss
|
NO
|
YES
|
YES
|
---
It should be pretty clear
that I am talking here about pure agnosticism, weak theism/atheism and strong
theism/atheism. Theists of a certain
stripe struggle understanding that not believing in a god and believing that a
god does not exist is not the same position (which they label as an epistemic
position rather than a doxic position).
Hopefully those theists can understand that the positions work perfectly
well if we are talking about smashing (or not smashing) an egg with a
sledgehammer. Let's modify the table, so
that we make the hittists theists and the missists atheists:
Know
God
|
Not
Know
|
Know
No God
|
|
Believe
God
|
YES
|
YES
|
NO
|
Not
Believe
|
NO
|
YES
|
NO
|
Believe
No God
|
NO
|
YES
|
YES
|
Modifying again to ram the
point home:
Know
God
|
Not
Know
|
Know
No God
|
|
Believe
God
|
Strong,
Hard or Gnostic Theist
|
Weak,
Soft or Agnostic Theist
|
NO
|
Not
Believe
|
NO
|
Pure
or Adoxic Agnostic
|
NO
|
Believe
No God
|
NO
|
Weak,
Soft or Agnostic Atheist
|
Strong,
Hard or Gnostic Atheist
|
---
We can make another
modification to the second last table to highlight a confusion that might lie
behind the theists' problem with the spectrum of atheistic non-belief (and no,
I am not going to try to introduce apatheism into the mix. How much, if at all, you care about the question
would introduce another axis - want god to exist (to some extent), not care, want god to not
exist (to some extent)):
Know
|
Not
Know
|
Know
Not
|
|
Believe
|
YES
|
YES
|
NO
|
Not
Believe
|
NO
|
YES
|
???
|
Believe
Not
|
NO
|
YES
|
YES
|
In informal English, it is
possible to say that you know that there is no god and also say that you do not
believe. This can trip you up when you
look at "Not Believe-Know Not" as a cell - it actually seems vaguely possible. I don't think this confusion would occur in most
other languages because they are structured differently and that it's the auxiliary
verb (do) that leads to this confusion in modern English. Strictly speaking, to know anything you must
believe it (albeit not necessarily in the religious sense of believing). What we also see here is an equivocation on the
word "believe" - if you are working with a strong, faith-like definition of "believe" then this cell would be workable. I, on the other hand, am using "believe" in a purely functional sense - meaning something along the lines of "hold to be true".
I am reasonably sure that a
substantial proportion of people, when trying to fill the table in this last
form, would at least pause for a moment when filling in the "Not
Believe-Know Not" cell, some would fill it with YES and then argue that
they are right. However, I reckon that the very same people would have no problem filling the table out correctly
when expressed in terms of hitting or missing an egg with a sledgehammer - because the definition of belief as approaching faith is not triggered in that example.
---
Some might wonder how this construct might align with Dawkin's spectrum of belief.
That spectrum is more probabilistic and the table would look something like
this:
Know
|
Not
Know
|
Know
Not
|
|
100%
god
|
YES
|
NO
|
NO
|
75-99%
god
|
NO
|
YES
|
NO
|
51-74%
god
|
NO
|
YES
|
NO
|
50%
god
|
NO
|
YES
|
NO
|
25-49%
god
|
NO
|
YES
|
NO
|
1-24%
god
|
NO
|
YES
|
NO
|
0%
god
|
NO
|
NO
|
YES
|
[I had written something here about the "0% god - Not Know" and "100% god - Not Know" cells, but it wasn't particularly important and I added confusion by misusing the term certainty. Hopefully people can work out why those cells change to NO so I don't really need to attempt a fumbling explanation.]
Note the difference in strength between what could be called "strong atheism" and "weak atheism". It can be as little as 1% or 0.01%. Alternatively, you could call "1-24% (chance of) god" strong atheism, or use some other low probability range if you prefer, the higher values would then be weak atheism and the zero point zero recurring percent would be reserved for people that we call "idiots". (Similarly anyone claiming a 100% certainty with respect to god would be an idiot, but we are generally encouraged to be more diplomatic when this sort of unrealistic certainty is expressed by a believer.)
Note the difference in strength between what could be called "strong atheism" and "weak atheism". It can be as little as 1% or 0.01%. Alternatively, you could call "1-24% (chance of) god" strong atheism, or use some other low probability range if you prefer, the higher values would then be weak atheism and the zero point zero recurring percent would be reserved for people that we call "idiots". (Similarly anyone claiming a 100% certainty with respect to god would be an idiot, but we are generally encouraged to be more diplomatic when this sort of unrealistic certainty is expressed by a believer.)
---
Hmmm. Anyone hungry for an omelette?