In
brief, I looked at the probabilistic thinking that underpins the standard Bayes
Theorem, the one that I can find in every single statistics text book I’ve
looked at, including those which are very much focussed on Bayesian
probability. The Bayes Theorem as
expressed by this equation is (adapted from a handy set of University of Washington lecture notes) using the assumption that
there are two mutually exclusive events, A1
and A2):
Pr(A1|B) =
Pr(A1) . Pr(B|A1)
-----------------------------
( Pr(A1) . Pr(B|A1)
+ Pr(A2) . Pr(B|A2) )
If
we replace A1 with R, A2
with not-R and B with B&E, this then
becomes:
Pr(R|(B&E)) =
Pr(R) . Pr((B&E)|R)
-----------------------------
Pr(R) . Pr((B&E)|R) +
Pr(not-R) . Pr((B&E)|not-R)
Craig’s
variation of the Bayes Theorem, however, looks like this (with variations
marked in bold
red):
Pr(R|(B&E)) =
Pr(R|B)
. Pr(E|B&R)
-----------------------------
Pr(R|B)
. Pr(E|B&R)
+ Pr(not-R|B) . Pr(E|B¬-R)
Both
these equations seem pretty terrifying, even the standard one.
In
order to clarify things a little, we will shortly return to the idea of
jellybeans. In Sweet Probability, we
had a jar with 100 jellybeans, 60 that contain Red material, 60 that contain yEllow
material and 60 that contain Blue material – with some overlap, obviously. The corresponding probabilities would be (see
the article for
my working):
Pr(R)=Pr(B)=Pr(E)=0.6
Pr(R∩B)=Pr(B∩E)=Pr(E∩R)=0.2
Pr(R∩B∩E)=0.1
I have
been told that the jellybean analogy totally misrepresents Craig’s argument, or
at least stretches the analogy until it was very close to breaking. Clearly the use of the analogy alone isn’t
going to wash.
My
response to this accusation has been to demand that my interlocutor produce a
derivation of Craig’s form of the Bayes Theorem, a demand that I have made
repeatedly and rather forcefully … a demand that has, at least so far, been met
with a ringing silence.
Therefore,
it seems, we have to do the work ourselves.
In
the diagram below I show the derivation of both the standard Bayes Theorem and
the version used by Craig (click on it for a larger version):
The
first three steps are common, and the fourth could be common, but I see no
benefit in replacing B with B&E until the
last step – unless your intention is to confuse.
The
only tricky thing that is done in this working is to use the very first
relationship Pr(X|Y)=Pr(X&Y)/Pr(Y) over and over again, sometimes forwards
and sometimes backwards. You end up with
a complex looking equation, but really what it gives you is no more
complex than what we have in the second line, the point in which we could
replace B with B&E to get:
In
our analogy, we already know that Pr(R&B&E)=0.1
so we just need to work out what the value of Pr(^R&B&E) is. Putting
this into words, we wish to work out the probability of selecting jellybean that
contains both Blue and yEllow jellybean material but not Red jellybean material. This eliminates all the red (20), orange
(10), purple (10) and white (10) jellybeans along with those that contain only
Blue and only yEllow jellybean material (20 and 20), leaving only the green
jellybeans, of which there are 10. So
Pr(^R&B&E)=0.1 which coincidentally is
the same value as Pr(R&B&E). Therefore Pr(R|B&E)=0.1/(0.1+0.1)=0.5
which is less than the inherent probability of R, Pr(R), before we
started.
But
this is, of course an unfair analogy.
The value of Pr(R) that Craig uses is the probability that a specific
person was resurrected. That’s a
miraculous thing and, by definition, miracles don’t occur with a probability of
six in ten (0.6) – they are much more likely to have a probability of one in a
million (0.000001) or even one in a billion (0.000000001). A resurrection is even less likely than that,
judging from the number of resurrected people we have today.
Note
that I am not talking about someone who almost dies, who is revived and might
come back with some interesting reports of an out of body experience – something
which is a little more common. I am
talking about someone who is well and truly dead, who is locked into a crypt
and who rises from the dead three days later.
Each year we have more than 50 million people who die. For the sake of the argument, let’s say that
each year we get 50 bona fide resurrections, which means that there is a one in
a million chance of getting resurrected and Pr(R)=0.000001. This is equivalent to having a jar with a
million jellybeans in it, of which only one contains Red jellybean material.
Turning
to B, we find that we have a disagreement.
What does this mean, exactly?
Craig tells us that B is “Background knowledge”. Now when I hear that, I think of the
knowledge that we as a species have access to if we choose to seek it out and,
in this specific context, it refers to the fact that there are no reliable
reports of people being resurrected.
However, I’ve been told that this is unfair because I am assuming
naturalism whereas, from what I can tell from the complainant’s argument, B “should” be construed as theism.
Ok –
but if that is the case, then it can’t be used in any argument proving the
existence of god. You cannot arrive at a
valid proof for the existence of anything if you’ve assumed it from
the start. This is why I give Craig the
benefit of the doubt and assume that B is just what we know, and therefore
P(B)=1.0 meaning that the likelihood of knowing what we know is one hundred per
cent. This is equivalent to B being the
likelihood of selecting a jellybean from a jar containing one million of them
and finding that it is a jellyBean. Thus
P(R|B)=0.000001 and our “Background knowledge” has had no effect on the
likelihood of a resurrection.
Now
finally, we have E. What does Craig
actually mean by this? He says it means
“Specific evidence (empty tomb, post-mortem appearances, etc.)” But how can we turn this into a
likelihood? Normally, when the Bayes
Theorem is applied, we talk about different events, or aspects of an event,
rather than “evidence”. In my example, I
link E to the likelihood of a selected jellybean containing yEllow jellybean
material. This is an “event” that is
linked to the jellybean being a jellyBean (B), but not to the jellybean
containing Red (R).
I
suspect, however, that we should look more at the likelihood of the “Specific
evidence” arising. What are the chances
that a book that is getting on for two millennia old contains the following
reports:
·
“On the Sunday after his crucifixion, Jesus’ tomb was found empty by a group
of his women followers”,
·
“On separate occasions different individuals and groups saw appearances of
Jesus alive after his death”, and
·
“The original disciples suddenly came to believe in the resurrection of
Jesus despite having every predisposition to the contrary”?
I’m
going to follow Plantinga’s example here and say that there are two options:
·
The reports are true, or
·
The reports are false (either due to outright
fabrication, delusion on the part of those making the reports or some mix of
muddled reporting that led to a false conclusions which were then reported
incredulously).
Since
there are two options, the probability of each is 0.5 (see Planting a Tiger for
an explanation of Plantigerant probability).
Therefore, P(E)=0.5 which is equivalent to half the jellybeans
containing yEllow jellybean material.
So,
once we have modified the analogy accordingly, we have a jar containing one
million jellybeans, one of which contains Red jellybean material –
P(R)=0.000001, one million of which are jellyBeans – P(B)=1.0 and five hundred
thousand of which contain yEllow jellybean material – P(E)=0.5 – but what we
don’t know is the distribution of yEllow and Red jellybean material.
Fortunately,
we can rely on Plantigerant probability again.
If a jellybean contains Red jellybean material then it will, again,
either contain yEllow jellybean material or it won’t. Therefore P(E|R)=0.5.
We
know that likelihood of a jellybean containing Red jellybean material (R) and
being a jellyBean (B) is the same as the likelihood of a jellybean containing
Red jellybean material, so P(R&B)=0.000001.
We know that the likelihood of a jellybean not containing Red jellybean
material is 999,999 to one, so P(^R)=0.999999 and jellybeans which don’t
contain Red jellybean material are nevertheless jellybeans so
P(^R&B)=0.999999.
Appealing
to Plantigerant probability once more, if a jellybean does not contain Red
jellybean material then it will either contain yEllow jellybean material or it
won’t. Therefore P(E|^R)=0.5
Using
the same logic as above, we know that P(E|^R&B)=0.5 and we now have all the
numbers we need to plug into Craig’s equation to get a result.
Which
means that P(R|B&E)=0.000001=P(R).
The
only way you can get this equation to change in Craig’s favour is to assume
that E has a likelihood that is higher than 0.5, which you would only do if you
already assume that the resurrection story is reflective of an actual
resurrection.
In
other words, a calculation of P(R|B&E) which results in a value that
approaches unity tells us nothing about the likelihood of the resurrection
story being true and everything about the assumptions of the person performing
that calculation.
---------------------------------------------
Something
that Craig says in his debate with Krauss now makes more sense:
So the question “Is There
Evidence for God?” isn’t really very debatable. Rather the really interesting
question is whether God’s existence is more probable than not. That is, is
Pr (G | E & B) > 0.5
?
Now I’ll leave it up to you to assess that probability. My
purpose in tonight’s debate is more modest: to share with you five pieces of
evidence each of which makes God’s existence more probable than it would have
been without it. Each of them is therefore evidence for God. Together they
provide powerful, cumulative evidence for theism.
Craig
is using exactly the same sort of argument that Richard Swinburne made, using
precisely the same sort of equation (although in the Krauss debate he just
threw it out there and made no effort whatsoever to explain what it was
supposed to mean).
When
you have worked it all through you begin to see that, in fact, it was pretty
cunning of Craig to leave it up to the listener to assess the probability,
since you’d end up with Pr(G|E&B) = Pr(G) which is a totally subjective
assessment based on whether or not you already believe in the god in question.